Volume 55 Number 16 Produced: Sun Jul 8 9:41:28 EDT 2007 Subjects Discussed In This Issue: Comparative Jurisprudence [Jay F. Shachter] ---------------------------------------------------------------------- From: Jay F. Shachter <jay@...> Date: Wed, 4 Jul 2007 18:47:40 +0000 (WET DST) Subject: Comparative Jurisprudence In v54n51, one of the contributors to this mailing list made the following observation: > ... My question, however, was about an Eved Canaani. In this case, > there seems to be ownership of the person. In thinking this through, > I have tried to draw an analogy to a member of the US Armed forces: he > or she is subject to orders, can be ordered into life threatening > situations, and can be forced to accept vaccinations. However, this > analogy doesn't really work since the armed forces do not "own" the > soldier's body. This is both legally and factually incorrect. I don't know how much interest there is in United States law among the international readership of this mailing list, but the above misstatement is reflective of three fallacies which may be profitably discussed here. First, the law. There are several places where the military law of the United States recognizes that a serviceman's body is, contrary to the assertion quoted above, the property of the United States government. If two sailors get drunk on shore leave and beat each other up, they can be charged under the provisions of 10 U.S.C. §908 with the crime of damaging military property. In fact, the same charge can apply to self-inflicted harm, even if unintended, so long as it is negligent. Thus, a serviceman who, e.g., goes to the beach on his day off, and gets himself badly sunburned, is subject to a charge of "damaging military property". There are several former members of the United States military on this mailing list (including at least one retiree who holds the rank of Colonel) so you can confirm this statement with other knowledgeable members of this mailing list. There are three errors of thinking that contribute to the above-quoted misstatement. One error is the notion that the United States Constitution (the Uniform Code Of Military Justice is limited only by the United States Constitution; it is not limited by any additional rights that may be granted by any State constitution), specifically, the Thirteenth Amendment, prohibits the ownership of people. It does not; it only prohibits slavery and involuntary servitude (except as punishment for crime). It does not state that you, or the government, cannot have a property interest in someone else's person. In fact, the common-law torts of loss of consortium, or wrongful death, imply a limited property right of sorts in someone else's person, and even full ownership rights are not explicitly prohibited by the Thirteenth Amendment, only slavery and involuntary servitude. The second error is the notion that the language of the Thirteenth Amendment is dispositive. It is not. The Thirteenth Amendment, despite its language, does not guarantee that there cannot legally be involuntary servitude in the United States. The courts can find that the Thirteenth Amendment prohibits involuntary servitude, whereas other parts of the Constitution permit it, whereupon the courts will declare that the Constitution is, to a certain limited extent, self-contradictory, and they will undertake to delineate the respective spheres wherein each contradictory clause is operative -- i.e., under what circumstances there can be no involuntary servitude, and under what circumstances there can be. And even if you cannot find any clause in the Constitution that contradicts the Thirteenth Amendment, you are not safe, and you have not been safe since the black day of Saturday, March 6, 1819, when John Marshall wrote the opinion in McCulloch v. Maryland (17 U.S. 316), and created the doctrine of "implied powers", under which powers can be imputed to the federal government that are not expressly stated in the Constitution. So, for example, the clause in Article 1, Section 8, which empowers Congress to raise and support Armies, can be construed to necessarily imply the power to raise and support armies by means of conscription, even though conscription is unquestionably involuntary servitude. The third error is the notion that the United States government, or any other government, is controlled by laws and by its Constitution. This is nonsense, and it is pernicious nonsense, because it is always dangerous to believe that which is untrue. Read Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214, and be forever disabused of the notion that there is such a thing among the Gentile nations as the rule of law. There is a certain kind of idiot who weeps over the clause in the constitution of the Weimar republic that authorized the chancellor to declare a state of emergency under certain circumstances, as if the German people would not have killed six million Jews, if only -- if only -- the constitution of the Weimar republic had lacked that clause. The truth is that German people killed six million Jews, and American people imprisoned their Japanese-American neighbors, because they wanted to, and what their constitutions said or didn't say did not matter at all. The United States federal government can do anything, except for a few acts that are forbidden to it by the Bill of Rights (see, e.g., Gonzales v. Raich, 545 U.S. 1, especially the dissent authored by Justice Thomas beginning on page 545 U.S. 57). From time to time, you hear what appear to be people saying things such as the United States federal government is a government of enumerated powers, but on closer inspection it always turns out that the parties uttering those statements are not people, but extraterrestrial aliens who resemble human beings morphologically, except that they do not have human brains inside their skulls. Instead of a human brain, these creatures have inside their skull an organ that makes it possible for them to believe that the interstate commerce clause empowers Congress to legislate what drugs you may put into your body, and that the slavery clause empowers Congress to legislate against racial discrimination (because acts of racial discrimination are the "badges of slavery"), and that the war clause empowers Congress to build interstate highways, and that there is something in the Constitution that empowers Congress to allocate funds for the relief of hurricane victims, and to fund school lunch programs, and to legislate against child labor, and to legislate against an 18-hour workday, and to require employers to provide unemployment insurance, and a minimum hourly wage. The truth is that none of these powers is granted by the Constitution, and no one cares that they are not granted by the Constitution, and no one, except for extraterrestrials, claims that they are. Knowledge of this fact provides important context to a study of Jewish law. The Karaite movement was not led by stupid people, and, although the history is not taught in yeshivot, for a time they encompassed the intellectual center of gravity of the Jewish nation. The growth of this movement was promoted by the quite accurate observation that Jewish laws, even those laws that are claimed to be Scriptural, sometimes appear to be very weakly related to the verses claimed to be the basis for them, like mountains suspended by a hair, or hanging in midair. For a superb treatment of this subject -- truly, I cannot praise it too highly -- the gentle reader is referred to mail.jewish v43n91 (http://www.ottmall.com/mj_ht_arch/v43/mj_v43i91.html). But the last word on a topic is never spoken, and a few more observations may be profitably made. Let's look at the exposition of Leviticus 19:14, a verse which admonishes us not to curse a deaf person. The halakha is that we may not curse anyone, neither deaf nor hearing. Why does the verse specify a deaf person? According to Midrash Leqax Tov, it is a simple a fortiori ("qal vxomer", in Hebrew): if you may not even curse a deaf person -- who cannot hear your curse -- then surely you may not curse anyone else. Leqax Tov, though, it not a basis for halakha, unlike, e.g., the Sifra, which is used by codifiers like Rambam as a source for the halakha, sometimes even in preference to the Talmuds. The Sifra says nothing about a qal vxomer. The Sifra also applies this verse to any person, whether deaf or not, but it states that the reason the verse mentions the deaf is that a deaf person is characterized by being alive -- just as you may not curse a deaf person, who is alive, so, too, you may not curse any other living person -- i.e., cursing dead people is not prohibited by this verse. Presumably, if the verse had simply told you not to curse anyone, you would not have known this, and you might have incorrectly thought that you were forbidden to curse dead people. The same exposition is found in the Mkhilta attributed to Rabbi Shim`on Bar Yoxai (not to be confused with the more familiar Mkhilta attributed to Rabbi Yishma`el) to Exodus 22:27. There seems to be a notable increase in entropy in this exposition of the verse, in the sense that, under this exposition, there are many different initial states that can lead to the same final state. The verse could have said, "Do not curse a lion tamer" or "Do not curse a chartered accountant", and you could still have said: it doesn't mean only a chartered accountant, it means all living people; just as a chartered accountant is alive, so, too, you may not curse anyone who is alive. But there is still no satisfactory explanation for why a deaf person is the example given by the verse. Such observations may lead you to entertain the notion that Jewish legal exegesis is, at times, forced and unnatural, the rabbis choosing their conclusions regardless of the language of the verse, deciding first what conclusion they want to reach, and then deciding how to derive that conclusion from the verse. When you find such thoughts welling up inside of you, I urge you to ask yourself: forced and unnatural, compared to what? Compared to the legal reasoning of the goyim? Ha! It is to laugh. Ha, I say. Remember Raich, remember Korematsu. Jewish legal exegesis is not merely the most intellectually honest legal exegesis in the world. It is the only intellectually honest legal exegesis in the world. Whenever I examine one of these apparently forced interpretations with a modicum of patience and humility, I find that the interpretation appears forced only because of the passage of time, and the consequent slow loss of context and of shared cultural literacy. In fact, the Sifra and the Mkhilta of Rabbi Shim`on Bar Yoxai assumed that the reader would understand -- and consequently left unstated, as not needing to be said -- that Leviticus 19:14 employs a qal vxomer. They were explaining why Scripture employs the deaf person as the lower bound of the range. If the universal set ranges from 1 to 100, and if there is a phenomenon that applies to all elements greater than 42, and if you can legitimately assume that if it applies to a lower number, it also applies to a higher number, then all you have to do, to describe the phenomenon, is to state that it applies to 43. From 43, you can deduce the range, 43 to 100, whereas from 52, you could only deduce the range, 52 to 100. Or, in the language of the Sifra -- Why 43? Because it is the smallest number greater than 42. The halakha of Leviticus 19:14 applies to all living people. For the purposes of the qal vxomer, a deaf person is the smallest element in this range, the example from which all others can be inferred. You can infer a chartered accountant from a deaf person, but you could not infer a deaf person from a chartered accountant, because the deaf person cannot even hear your curse, whereas the chartered accountant can. As the example has, I hope, indicated, Jewish legal discourse is sometimes hard to understand, because of the immense passage of time that has occurred between now and when the law was first given to us, but it is not dishonest, and in that regard it is dissimilar from the legal discourse of every other nation in the world, which is grossly dishonest. That is why involvement in secular law is so morally corrosive, and involvement in Jewish law is not. Jay F. ("Yaakov") Shachter 6424 N Whipple St Chicago IL 60645-4111 (1-773)7613784 <jay@...> http://m5.chicago.il.us ----------------------------------------------------------------------
End of Volume 55 Issue 16